Karl Marx wrote The Eighteenth
Brumaire of Louis Napoleon as a
history of the French Revolution of 1848 in terms of class warfare. Its oft quoted first two
sentences read, “Hegel
remarks somewhere
that
all great world-historic facts and personages appear, so to speak,
twice. He forgot to add: the first time as tragedy, the second time
as farce.” He refers here to the French Revolutions of 1789 and
1848. The first is a tragedy because, according to Marx, power
changed hands from the old aristocracy to the rising bourgeoisie. The
second is a farce because power fell into the hands of the buffoon,
Louis Napoleon but means of production did not change hands from one
class to another. For although the Paris proletariat did hold power
for a brief time in February, 1848, a counterrevolution involving
almost all classes against the proletariat, allowed Louis Napoleon,
the representative of the lumpen
proletariat,
to take power and rule for many years. Though different in kind both
revolutions are stage plays, but, Marx hopes, the real revolution,
the “social revolution of the nineteenth century, won't be.
Marx
chuckles at the bourgeoisie for being so afraid of the proletariat
that it allows itself to fall into barbarism, demolishing what Marx
thinks of as the bourgeois goal, the bourgeois republic. “The
French bourgeoisie had long ago found the solution to Napoleon’s
dilemma: 'In fifty years Europe will be republican or Cossack.' It
solved it in the “Cossack republic.” No Circe using black magic
has distorted that work of art, the bourgeois republic, into a
monstrous shape. That republic has lost nothing but the semblance of
respectability.” Marx expects this monstrous specter to inspire the
“social revolution of the nineteenth century.” He explains that
the proletariat didn't revolt after Dec 2 when Louis Napoleon
overthrew the vestiges of the bourgeois republic because the whole
remainder of the nation ganged up against it— including the
peasantry. But also, he asserts, the proletariat will not be able to
replay a past stage play, but must invent itself as it goes along. In
spite of this hiccup, the history fits neatly into Hegelian terms.
Contradictions within the bourgeois republic lead it to throw itself
into the arms of Louis Napoleon, described as what most of us would
see as a proto-Nazi. With the Bourgeois Republic now revealed as a
monstrosity, the social revolution of the nineteenth century cannot
be far off.
Marx
adopted the word “proletariat” to identify the working class and
with it he describes history as, not a story about political actors,
but class warfare. Aristocracy, bourgeoisie, proletariat, and lumpen
proletariat—these are the actors on the world historical stage.
Since then, this description has been persuasive both to the “left”
and to the “right.” It is class war that allows Marx to describe
the revolution of 1789 as tragedy and that of 1848 as farce. The
idea that the first French Revolution, that of 1789, was the
“Bourgeois Revolution,” as Marx described it, has taken root.
Most on the left now think of that revolution as something of a
preliminary revolution, with the final revolution, the proletarian
revolution, still to be accomplished. To be sure, with Marx's
demonization, the word “proletariat” can no longer be used, but
the idea remains. “The people” or “the 99%” now substitute
for it. The distinction is one of class.
But
those who actually participated in the French Revolution did not
think of it in class terms. The Marquis de Lafayette wrote the
Declaration of the Rights of Man with the help of Thomas Jefferson.
Neither could be accused of membership in the bourgeoisie. The
Declaration of the Rights of Man spoke of universal human equality.
Marx comments that classes, such as the landed peasantry, who
supported the first revolution, turned against the Paris proletariat
in the second because they had benefited from the “bourgeois
republic.” “While the Paris proletariat still reveled in the
vision of the wide prospects that had opened before it and indulged
in seriously meant discussions of social problems, the old powers of
society had grouped themselves, assembled, reflected, and found
unexpected support in the mass of the nation, the peasants and petty
bourgeois, who all at once stormed onto the political stage after the
barriers of the July Monarchy had fallen.” Is this an alliance
between classes or a counter revolution that is classless?
What
is perhaps forgotten now is the considerable sympathy the original
French Revolution had within the European aristocracy, supposedly its
enemy. Lafayette was of the aristocracy.
Lord Stanhope, chairman of “The Revolution Society” founded in
honor of the English Revolution of 1688 expressed support for the
French Revolution, as did the other members of the society in 1790.
To be sure he was later ostracized for his sympathies, but their
early acceptance reflects some aristocratic sympathy with the
original idealism of the Revolution.
The
French Revolution of 1789 did abolish privileges of the aristocracy
and thus opened the way for freer commercial flow. In that sense it
was a bourgeois revolution. But it also deprived the nobles of
property, one of Burke's major objections, and thus was a peasant
revolution. The sentiments expressed in the Declaration of the Rights
of Man were of universal human equality, not class war. Even Burke
admitted sympathy for these sentiments.”Those who cultivate the
memory of our Revolution [the English Revolution of 1688] and those
who are attached to the constitution of this kingdom will take good
care how they are involved with persons who, under the pretext of
zeal toward the Revolution and constitution, too frequently wander
from their true principles and are ready on every occasion to depart
from the firm but cautious and deliberate spirit which produced the
one, and which presides in the other.”
But
the word “equality” meant different things to different people.
Burke's equality was what he called moral equality. He was convinced
that the French Revolution betrayed the sentiments it professed to
uphold. Burke understood, as anyone who thinks about it must, that an
idea of universal equality in everything is a chimera. Nature bestows
gifts unequally, including the gift for amassing property. Burke
believed in another interpretation of these sentiments. With his
“moral equality” “you would have
had a protected, satisfied, laborious, and obedient people, taught to
seek and to recognize the happiness that is to be found by virtue in
all conditions; in which consists the true moral equality of mankind,
and not in that monstrous fiction which, by inspiring false ideas and
vain expectations into men destined to travel in the obscure walk of
laborious life, serves only to aggravate and embitter that real
inequality which it never can remove, and which the order of civil
life establishes as much for the benefit of those whom it must leave
in a humble state as those whom it is able to exalt to a condition
more splendid, but not more happy.” Burke, it seems, hoped
to convince the people that they were happy in their humble position,
a sentiment that surely must have been impossible to inculcate in the
bustling new-born entrepreneurial capitalism of the nineteenth
century. Burke feared popular dissatisfaction and seems not to have
anticipated the overweening ambition free enterprise inspired and
through which the rising bourgeoisie must inevitably have destroyed
the privileges of the nobility. Neither he nor Marx thought equality
might mean equality of opportunity to develop one's talents.
Marx,
of course, thought of these sentiments as costume.
The
classic description of universal human equality is that in the
American Declaration of Independence. “We hold these truths to be
self-evident, that all men are created equal.” Were equality
identified with equality of financial means, social position, or
natural endowments the statement would be absurd, not “self
evident.” The statement, couched as it is in the logical language
of “self-evident truths” is clearly an expression of the
Enlightenment. What it objects to is privileges bestowed upon the
scions of certain families that give them unfair advantages. Those
informed by the Enlightenment, as all of us now are, saw human beings
as a collection of talents, the primary being that of reason.
Self-evident equality at creation could only mean equality at naked
birth, an equality of opportunity for “life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness,” that is, the development of these talents
for one's own benefit. Given an image of man naked in the state of
nature, these truths do, indeed, seem self-evident.
Marx
saw the bourgeoisie's curious political incompetence that contrasted
sharply with their rise in wealth. In spite of the nobility's
apparent recovery of power after the Congress of Vienna and other
similar congresses following Napoleon's defeat, the bourgeoisie
retained their freedom of activity under the restored monarchy. Louis
Philippe was known as the bourgeois monarch. Their riches continued
to grow, but curiously, they remained politically clownish, as Marx
saw so clearly in the Revolution of 1848.
The boredom and corruption Marx identifies with the bourgeois
republic was something of a commonplace. Moliere's Bourgeois
Gentilhomme, presented more than 100 years earlier, had satirized
the bourgeois mercilessly. The well-known bourgeois passion for
social climbing revealed the barren nature of bourgeois life and its
bad conscience. The first thing the successful bourgeois wanted to do
was escape being bourgeois. He aspired to imitate the decadent
nobility unless he could, through his wealth, actually join them. His
excursions into the demimonde to give life spice were also well
known. Marx mocked the bourgeoisie for having virtually thrown power
to Louis Napoleon in fear after the brief appearance the the Paris
proletariat on the stage of history. But this also shows the enormous
bourgeois political inferiority complex. Statesmen were subtle,
unlike the fumbling bourgeois gentilhomme. The whole Romantic
movement was an attempt to find an escape through imagination to a
life more alive than what bourgeois society had to offer. The
“bourgeois gentleman,” an oxymoron, hardly had the courage, let
alone the imagination, to take political power in spite of his
burgeoning wealth.
Hannah
Arendt notes the bourgeoisie's political backwardness. She writes in
Origins of Totalitarianism, “The central inner-European event of
the imperialist period [1884-1914] was the political emancipation of
the bourgeoisie, which up to then had been the first class in history
to achieve economic pre-eminence without aspiring to political rule.”
She attributes this sudden arrival on the political stage to the
bourgeoisie's need to use the army to rule foreign countries, a
project in direct contradiction to the raison d'être
of the nation state. For the nation justifies its existence as
protection for the particular way of life of a “volk” or nation,
as Burke would have it. The English nation-state protects the rights
and customs of Englishmen, not the universal rights of men. It has no
business ruling others with other customs. She recounts the state's
resistance to the “megalomania of imperialist aspirations.” But
capitalism set free must expand and will soon reach the borders of
the nation-state and need to go beyond them. Hence imperialism. Of
course the true irony was that the nation state's imperial venture
infected the subject countries with the passion for their own nation,
inspiring inevitable revolution.
But
where did this bourgeois megalomania come from? Arendt traces it to
Hobbes, and she is undoubtedly right. But there is nothing further
from Hobbes than the Declaration of the Rights of Man. Nothing
could contrast more with Hobbes's “nasty, brutish, short” human
life than that of a man in the state of nature developing his talents
to achieve “happiness.” How did Europe get from the “new dawn”
of the French Revolution to absolute nihilism of the imperial
bourgeois period? Well, there is not much difference between nihilism
and materialism. Arendt writes, “ For power left to itself can
achieve nothing but more power, and violence administered for power's
(and not for law's ) sake turns into a destructive principle that
will not stop until there is nothing left to violate.” And so
imperialism has proved in fact. But after Marx what else was there
but power and more power, wealth and more wealth.
The
French revolutions of 1830 and 1848 were again in the name of the
principles of 1789. But Marx's characterization of the revolution of
1848 as a farce because it failed to transfer power to the Paris
proletariat changed all that. For it is through this history that
Marx changed the idea of revolution from a fight for universal human
equality to class warfare. Behind this is Marx's materialist
philosophy, the idea that all culture and value were but disguise for
the real truth, namely, the identity of who controlled the means of
production. High ideals were the costume of tragedy or farce
depending upon which class ended up with the means of production at
the end.
Such
interpretation appealed to leftist historians who could push aside
all that refinement of manners they were not heir to and look only at
the cold hard material facts: who controls what. But what no one
seems to have realized is just what a boon such interpretation was to
the bourgeoisie. They too stumbled over their clumsy manners. This
interpretation set them free from the self-doubt of the uncultured
and the moral qualms that might arise from their possession of “dark
satanic mills” while professing a belief in universal human
equality. They were now warriors in a class war and all that could be
pushed aside. All that was real was money and power, and that was
what they had in spades. The bourgeois's clumsiness, his lack of
style, the emptiness of his life, was irrelevant. Manners, honor,
morals were but window dressing. They saw through it to the truth.
Boredom evaporated in the frisson of unvarnished savagery that was
class warfare. Their inferiority complex had kept them away from
politics, but in the late nineteenth century they commandeered the
machinery of the nation state for imperialist purposes with ruthless
glee. For there was nothing to hold them back.
Since
revolution was class war, not a fight for universal human dignity,
all was fair. Since power and wealth was everything, why should the
bourgeoisie relinquish it to another class? In a war for wealth and
power neither side has the moral high ground. Marx's labor theory of
value does not succeed in persuading anyone of the justice of the
proletariat's cause. The Congresses that followed Napoleon's defeat,
through which Metternich set up the nation state system that
continues in a hollowed out way today, countered the revolutionary
sentiments of the French Revolution by embracing, not rejecting them.
Friedrich von Gentz, Metternich's secretary, was a Burkean, and had
published a pamphlet, Die Historisches Journal which was
nothing but a translation of Burke's works. The Burkean nation-state
system countered the inflammatory Enlightenment sentiment for
universal equality by claiming it could only be achieved through the
nation state. Freedoms became “our” freedoms. The nation state,
the bourgeois republic, proclaimed itself the protector of human (now
English) rights. At the same time the parliamentary system exhausted
the revolutionary energy in procedural wrangling. The courts, too,
exhausted petitioners for justice as Dickens describes in Bleak
House. Nationalists did not pretend that the
revolutionary sentiment was nothing but a costume concealing the
reality of class warfare, but fed hopes for realizing these ideals
into a system that choked them with red tape. In such a system
demands for equality, when they grew too hot, could not be so easily
ignored. The American civil rights movement could succeed, if only
in a limited way, because it's demand for equality of treatment
repeated the noble hopes of the American and first French Revolutions
that the United States still clung too, however precariously.
Once
revolution became class war, and the bourgeoisie became political,
it's embarrassment over the “monstrous nature” of the bourgeois
republic vanished. Marx thought the exposure of this monstrous
character would doom the republic. What he failed to note was that
his own materialism made this monstrosity as much of a costume as
were the high flown sentiments of the first French Revolution.
Everything was but cover for power and wealth hunger. The bourgeoisie
proved quite indifferent to the horrors they perpetrated. War was,
after all, war. They pursued the ever more ghastly wars with aplomb,
focusing entirely on the prize, their own power and wealth. The
revolutionary cry, once “liberté, égalité, fraternité,,”
had become “show me the money.”
One
can only wonder what might have been had the revolutions that
continued through the nineteenth century remained revolutions for
universal human equality. Had equality been understood not as a
requirement for dispossessing the bourgeoisie, but as rather assuring
fairness of opportunity, the outcome might have been different. Marx
was certainly not wrong in seeing class war in the social
relationships mushrooming in the nineteenth century, but class war
need not have become the central theme of revolution. Dickens, who
saw all the horrors of capitalism better than almost anyone, to the
surprise of many, was horrified by class warfare. In his report, “On
Strike,” of the Preston strike in 1854 he wrote, “Masters right
or men right masters wrong or men wrong both right or both wrong
there is certain ruin to both in the continuance or frequent revival
of this breach. And from the ever widening circle of their decay what
drop in the social ocean shall be free?”
If
equality of opportunity had remained the theme of revolution, it
still would have required some redistribution of property, for no one
can expect children growing up in poverty to “realize their
potential.” Arendt attributes the bourgeois adaptation of their
rapacious ethic to their political isolation, and this does seem
plausible. But in the Canut revolts in Lyon, surely events that can
be seen as class warfare, the mill owners claimed the workers were
violating the principles of the French Revolution. That the
bourgeoisie would have acquiesced to this lesser level of property
redistribution seems doubtful from our perspective. But we are
looking from the well armed turrets of post Marxist capitalist
society and are primed to launch our own attacks in the war of all
against all. Had the bourgeoisie retained their sense of the
emptiness of bourgeois existence and the rightness of the principles
of the first French Revolution they might have seen the state as more
than just a police force and been more inclined to use some of their
wealth for the furtherance of universal human equality, seen as
equality of opportunity. After all it was because of the uprising in
the name of this equality that they realized their power in the first
place, and the talents thus fostered would have been in their
service.
No comments:
Post a Comment